Your web browser is out of date. Update your browser for more security, speed and the best experience on this site.

Update your browser

Last Days: Caring for the Terminally Ill

The Body: Issue Four

David Albert Jones

Nicholas Tonti-Filippini, About Bioethics: Volume 2—Caring for People who are Sick or Dying (Connor Court Publishing Pty Ltd, 2013).

In the first volume of this series, which was concerned with theoretical foundations of bioethics, bioethicist Nicholas Tonti-Filippini criticised various attempts of other Catholic thinkers to present bioethics by appeal to pure reason alone within a culture in which religion is increasingly marginalised from public life. Instead, he argued, Catholics should be prepared to “participate in public debate openly as Christians rather than trying to engage in pure reason. I would suggest that we should be open about our faith because subterfuge is beneath our dignity and in any case, would only breed suspicion” (vol. 1, p. 61). Such exhortation would be vain if the author did not also attempt to show, by example, how a Catholic thinker might engage with specific ethical questions in a way that was both open about his or her faith perspective and which was addressed to a wider public audience and not only to his or her co-religionists.

In Volume 2 Tonti-Filippini shows how the approach he advocates can be applied to the ethics of caring for people who are sick or dying. This volume covers issues such as “Not for Resuscitation” orders (what in the United Kingdom would usually be called Do Not Attempt Cardio-Pulmonary Resuscitation, DNACPR); tube feeding and refusals of food and water; euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide; advanced and proxy decision making; and psychiatric interventions that alter personality.

How, in practise, does Tonti-Filippini approach these topics? The answer, at its most general, is by mixing reflection on philosophical and theological principles, attention to clinical detail and reflection on his own experience. By this is not meant the supposed raw unmediated experience and sense perceptions appealed to by philosophical empiricists. Tonti-Filippini rather mixes argument (and it is important that his approach involves appeal to reason and argument) with reflection on his own experience as he understands it, that is, reflection on his story which is a narrative involving others and involving faith.

Such an approach is particularly effective in Tonti-Filippini’s case because of the impressive character of his own story. He is a man who is very ill, who has been near death many times, and who has been dependent on dialysis three times a week for the past twenty years. When he speaks of the experience of patients, he does so from the perspective of personal knowledge. This is best illustrated by example. When discussing the ways in which society often places further burdens on those who are ill and who require healthcare, Tonti-Filippini writes of how “for several years, until I objected, I received from my health insurer a letter that tells me how much it costs the fund to maintain my healthcare” (112).

Again, when discussing the issue of DNACPR, Tonti-Filippini writes of how,

recently, I suffered double pneumonia for which I was hospitalised including two days in intensive care. While there I was asked by a senior physician whether I would like not to be resuscitated in the event of a cardiac or respiratory arrest. At the time my breathing was machine-assisted, and I was in a state of acute distress and struggling to keep my oxygen saturation at a reasonable level. It was both confronting and demoralising to be asked that question, at a time of acute illness, implying as he did by his question that my plight might be hopeless… I was not really in a fit state at that time to manage his suggestion. Thankfully, I had previously completed some advice for end of life care… I referred him to that. (174)

Tonti-Filippini is aware that his experience is personal and in some respects unusual. His wife is a doctor and, due to his professional work as a bioethicist, he too is familiar with the working of a healthcare system more than many patients would be. He is also a practicing Catholic, thinking within a particular intellectual tradition and living within a particular faith community. He offers his reflective experience, therefore, not as one pretending to speak for everyone but as “an offering to be considered alongside the many other voices on these issues” (200).

It is where Tonti-Filippini draws on personal experience, together with philosophical and ethical reflection, that he is most persuasive. This is not to say that his discussion of other topics is without merit, but for this reader, at least, the greatest contribution of this book is the personal perspective the author brings to the discussion.

Tonti-Filippini’s interests shape the content of this volume. While it is ostensibly about “caring for people who are sick” and not only those who are dying (or whose sickness is life-threatening) most of the volume is in fact concerned with issues related to treatment and care at the end of life. The discussion of the ethics of mental healthcare (in chapter 4) felt like an extended digression and the volume contains very little discussion of, for example, the health needs of people with learning disabilities, or the genetic factors that cause disease and the ethical issues that are raised as it becomes possible to identify these factors. It is facile to criticise a book for what it does not contain, as it can always be said of any book that it does not cover this or that topic. My comment is intended only as a gentle forewarning for the potential reader. This volume is not about sickness in general but primarily concerned with sickness that might lead to death, though it also has a chapter about mental illness.

As there is a certain arbitrariness in the choice of topics treated in this volume so there is also an unevenness in the way the topics are treated and the style of writing. This is not a monograph that has been conceived in advance and then written as a coherent whole. It is rather an amalgam drawn from work that Tonti-Filippini has done throughout his career in articles, talks, or reports. The chapters thus switch from philosophical analysis, to personal experience, to theological reflection, to lists of considerations as one might find in an official report or a code of practice. This material is not always well integrated and it is not transparent why items are included or neglected from various lists. Occasionally the lists even seem to contradict one another, for example, “intellectual disability” is listed as a category in the classification systems for mental illness (152) and on the next page is listed as a condition of a person who is “not to be considered as mentally ill” (153). There is no discussion of this discrepancy.

There is also unevenness in the level of the theological material so that, for example, the contrast of Augustine and Thomas Aquinas on the Holy Trinity (166) is overdrawn and would be difficult to justify from their writings.

This volume would no doubt have benefitted from a longer gestation and a more thorough reworking and restructuring of material. However, the compromises evident in its production are perhaps expressive of the situation and thus the perspective of the author, and it is this perspective that gives the volume its value. In any case, this volume is a great contribution to Catholic bioethics, one that I am sure I will use in teaching, will recommend to others, and will return to in my own reflections.

I would draw attention in particular to the excellent discussion of euthanasia and assisted suicide (95ff.) and especially the personal perspective (110‒12) that completes that section. There is also a very well-balanced discussion of future care planning (140‒47) which is illuminated further when Tonti-Filippini shares the instructions that he drew up to cover his own future care. Among the provisions is the following paragraph:

6. If I suffer from cognitive impairment to such an extent that I can no longer understand the purpose of haemodialysis and this is a cause of distress I would want effective, non-burdensome treatment and care that is reasonably available to be continued, but would not want haemodialysis to be persisted with, if that decision was acceptable to my senior available next of kin. (199)

What impressed me most about this provision was the subtlety of the qualifications, not only the clarity about why haemodialysis might become burdensome (which bears not a trace of lack of respect for life with cognitive impairment) but also the last qualification which shows concern for the impact of the decision on the next of kin. Thus Tonti-Filippini shows not only how one can care for people who are sick or dying but also how those who are sick or dying can care for those around them. He shows how such care by one who is sick involves, among other things, a determination to value one’s own life not less than it is valued by others.


David Albert Jones is Director of the Anscombe Bioethics Centre, Oxford; Research Fellow at Blackfriars Hall, Oxford; and Visiting Professor at St Mary’s University College, Twickenham.

Keep reading! Click here to read our next article, Trauma and the Body.

David Albert Jones is the Director of the Anscombe Bioethics Centre in Oxford, Research Fellow in Bioethics at Blackfriars Hall, Oxford, Visiting Professor at St Mary's University College, Twickenham.

Posted on March 19, 2019

Recommended Reading

The Abolition of Mother

Julia Palmieri

Based on the cover, readers might think that Claire Horn’s debut book is about the miraculous event that is pregnancy and birth. Although it does touch upon these subjects, Eve: The Disobedient Future of Birth is rather about artificial gestation and the ways in which this technology could be used to advance progressive ideals or, conversely, used to reinforce regressive ends. The author, Claire Horn, is a feminist scholar and legal researcher who studies law and policy surrounding pregnancy, abortion, and reproductive rights. The omissions and assumptions of her book are startling.

Read Full Article
Hans Memling, "The Last Judgment" (detail)

Eschatology: Dying to Live

Andrew Kaethler

The Swiss Protestant theologian Karl Barth famously wrote, “Christianity which is not wholly eschatology and nothing but eschatology has nothing to do with Christ.” Isn’t Barth overstating the point? If he is not, then it seems fair to say that Christianity has little to do with this life. As the Catechism of the Catholic Church sets out, “Eschatology refers to the area of Christian faith which is concerned about ‘the last things,’ and the coming of Jesus on ‘the last day’: our human destiny, death, judgment, resurrection of the body, heaven, purgatory, and hell—all of which are contained in the final articles of the Creed.” What does hell, to choose but one of the “last things,” have to do with the present?

Read Full Article

A Friendship Bridging Earth and Heaven

Kelly Lindquist-Ray

Two months after my husband Ian died, I found myself re-reading Plato’s Republic with my fellow students at St. John’s College. I had gone back to the master’s program to finish my degree (in order to better support our seven children going forward), as well as to re-read the books that my husband Ian loved, and to have some time to reflect on the last year and a half of our lives together. Ian found out he was sick with leukemia on March 24th, 2021. Almost 80 years earlier, on that same day, a devout Catholic family, along with the Jewish neighbors they had been hiding on their farm, were killed in Poland by the Nazis.

Read Full Article
Humanum: Issues in Family, Culture & Science
Pontifical John Paul II Institute for Studies on Marriage and Family
620 Michigan Ave. N.E. (McGivney Hall)
Washington, DC 20064