Your web browser is out of date. Update your browser for more security, speed and the best experience on this site.

Update your browser
Mary Peterson, The Worker

Automation *versus* Artistry: On the "De-skilling" of the Workplace

Work: Issue One

John Laracy

Nicholas Carr, The Glass Cage: How Our Computers Are Changing Us (W.W. Norton & Co., 2014).

In The Glass Cage: How Our Computers Are Changing Us, technology writer Nicholas Carr raises a timely question: Are computers affecting human lives for better or worse? He shows how computer automation is changing the way we work. Computers produce more at ever-faster rates, but they may also make the work itself less enriching. Carr is best-known for his essay in The Atlantic, “Is Google Making Us Stupid?” (2008), and his book that deepens its argument, The Shallows: How the Internet is Changing the Way We Think, Read and Remember, which was a finalist for a 2011 Pulitzer Prize. Drawing on scientific research, especially social science, as well as philosophy, history, and literature, he challenges popular attitudes toward technology today. Some think technological “progress” is inherently good. Others think that technology is morally neutral—that its value depends wholly on how humans choose to use it. Yet Carr argues that Google, for example, inclines users to seek superficial information to the detriment of the learning-process itself (cf. Glass Cage, 78‒80). Similarly, computer automation tends to transform work from being a creative encounter into a mere means to a pre-programmed end.

In The Glass Cage, Carr explains that an “automated system” is a computer with a “sensing mechanism,” which gathers data from the external environment, and includes a “feedback method” that adjusts calculations based on the accumulated data (36). Automation simulates—and consequently displaces—actual intelligence and decision-making in the workplace: “The person operating the computer is left to play the role of a high-tech clerk” (67). This leads to the “de-skilling” of workers and, in turn, greater complacency and dependency on computers. In short, “automation breeds automation” (202). The increasing automation of everyday tasks—as we move from GPS in the car to Google’s self-driving car—seems to make life safer and less burdensome. Carr points out, however, that the interdependence of automated systems, connecting business and politics to everyday life, may lead to “cascading failures” in which small glitches lead to systemic breakdown (155). Our growing complacency toward automation makes us vulnerable to unforeseeable, large-scale emergencies. He cites a recent example that hits close to home: “Miscalculations of risk, exacerbated by high-speed computerized trading programs, played a major role in the near meltdown of the world financial system in 2008” (77).

Carr’s primary and more insightful criticism of automation is that it diminishes the quality of work, draining it of thought and “artistry” (85). To be clear, he is not critical of machinery as such but favors the use of tools that enhance the human experience of work itself. For example, he contrasts the skilled “machinist,” whose work is made more challenging by use of power hand-tools, with a “machine operator” who passively monitors a factory computer (111). Carr pays considerable attention to the advanced automation of airplanes (the “Glass Cage” of the title derives from the name for computerized cockpits: “a glass cockpit” [63]). He suggests that the pilot with some manual control of the plane, rather than one relying wholly on computers, is not only the happier pilot, but also the better one, ready to respond to unforeseen problems. Likewise, the doctor reliant on the guidance of an electronic medical-records system is less equipped to attend to the patient as a whole person (93ff.), and the architect dependent on advanced CAD (computer-aided design) software may lose his ability “to imagine the human qualities of their buildings” (145). In accord with Catholic social teaching (see Gaudium et spes, 1 and Laborem Exercens, 9), Carr thinks that work is integral to human dignity and that it is more fulfilling when it elicits our creativity by challenging us without overburdening us.

His philosophical perspective is a realist one that acknowledges the fundamental role of the body in human action and thought: “We’re real beings in real bodies in real places” (131; also see 148, 232). Humans are meant to know reality, and we know it by interacting with our physical surroundings. To put his view of work in classically metaphysical terms: the physical movement of work toward its intended end is itself a necessary and desirable dimension of that completed actuality (see 132). The joy of flying an airplane, for instance, is intrinsic to the pilot’s work of delivering passengers to their destination. Attentive care for the embodied person is intrinsic to the doctor’s work of improving health. Creative sketching is intrinsic to the work of architectural planning. Bodily labor, in general, is “a form of contemplation, a way of seeing the world face-to-face rather than through a glass” (214). By contrast to this rich immediacy, the constant mediation of computer screens distances us from reality, “making our lives more programmatic” (199; see 151). Restrained in tone and lacking apparent ideology, Carr’s thoughtfulness nonetheless leads him to a grim assessment: “[…] the automation of mental labor […] may end up eroding one of the foundations of culture itself: our desire to understand the world” (123).

Carr emphasizes that we must therefore cast a critical eye on every new form of technology, yet one wonders if he is sufficiently critical in the end. Attempting to accommodate some form of automation, he expresses approval of “human-centered automation,” designed to interact with, adapt to, and enhance the human worker: “Some early users of the systems report that they feel as though they’re collaborating with a colleague rather than operating a machine” (165). But this sort of automation, giving the illusion of interpersonal collaboration, might be most dangerous of all. As Pope John Paul II writes in the opening of Laborem Exercens, “work bears a particular mark of man and of humanity, the mark of a person operating within a community of persons.” If automation tends to displace what it attempts to simulate, as Carr reveals, should we not avoid this “adaptive automation,” lest it displace community? Carr never addresses this problem.

Similarly, he raises an important ethical issue about automated “decision-making” but fails to reach clarity on it. Google’s self-driving car, he points out, will need to be programmed to make instantaneous “decisions” about life and death (186‒89). Let us say that a child suddenly walks into the path of a self-driving car, leaving insufficient time to brake. Should the car swerve violently to save the child and risk the life of the driver? What if there were several passengers in the car—should that alter the car’s response? Carr exposes the conundrum generated by such automation: who should program these moral decisions and what criterion should they use? Yet he skirts a deeper question, without raising it explicitly: should this kind of automation exist at all? Perhaps driving should be left to a driver, who can assume direct responsibility for the consequences. Likewise, perhaps “lethal autonomous robots (LARs),” designed to act like soldiers in the battlefield, should not exist at all. Machines should not “decide” whether or not to pull the trigger on a possible enemy. Indeed, they cannot actually decide. Soldiers must not be removed from the work of soldiering. Nor, more generally, should “programmed morality” displace actual, real-time moral decisions, lest we begin to forget that we humans are the moral agents.

On the whole, The Glass Cage succeeds in showing, quite vividly, how expanding automation is displacing human work to our detriment. But this reader would recommend a firmer readiness to completely reject certain forms of automation. If society continues to uncritically embrace it, one should be ready to live differently than most, so as to recover an essentially human way of life. Carr does not draw out some of the important ethical implications of his largely accurate cultural assessment. A more minor complaint: The Glass Cage lacks any clear structure and reads more like a series of essays. Its breezy style will please some and bother others. Regardless, one cannot help but admire Carr’s capacity to raise profound questions about technology in such an accessible way.

John Laracy is a PhD candidate at the John Paul II Institute, soon to complete his dissertation on love as “event” in Hans Urs von Balthasar’s Trinitarian theology.





Keep reading! The next article in this issue is, Do We Need to Re-Think Modern Economics? by Roy Peachey

John Laracy is an assistant professor of Religion at Seton Hall University and received his PhD from the John Paul II Institute in 2018 for his dissertation “Divine Love as Event: A Study in the Trinitarian Theology of Hans Urs von Balthasar.”

Posted on May 30, 2017

Recommended Reading

Why We Live in a World of Machines

Georges Bernanos

George Bernanos (1888–1948) was a French novelist, essayist, and patriot, whose Catholic faith inspired in him a deep concern for the condition of man in modern society. When younger, Bernanos was drawn to the idealism of modern political movements whose promises of reform he later disavowed, expressing his disillusionment with these movements in a collection of "Last Essays" assembled in the final years of his life. These essays express Bernanos' conviction that revolutionary politics was just as much animated by the anti-humanist spirit that had contributed to the decomposition of European civilization.

Read Full Article
"The Perry sisters help maintain the vegetable garden on the property of the Dominion Arsenals Ltd. plant, 1942" (Courtesy of LibraryArchives)

The Machine vs. the Garden: What Working with Plants Has Taught Me

Renaud Beauchard

In a series of memorable essays, Paul Kingsnorth narrates what he calls “The Tale of the Machine,” of which AI is only the most recent incarnation. Kingsnorth defines the Machine as “the nexus of power, wealth, ideology and technology” that has emerged to “replace nature with technology, and to rebuild the world in purely human shape, the better to fulfill the most ancient human dream: to become gods.” We are, as Kingsnorth puts it, “unable to escape our total absorption by this thing, as we are reaching the point where its control over nature, both wild and human, is becoming unstoppable.”

Read Full Article

Can We "Find" Meaning?

Christopher Seith

I wonder if it is accurate to speak of a “loss” of meaning in our lives. Or, for that matter, I wonder if it is accurate to speak of “finding” meaning. These words, losing and finding, imply that meaning is “out there,” perhaps waiting, or hiding, and one need only look in the right places to find it. Certainly, this is how many of us respond to the desire for meaning in our lives. We spend our time in an anxious search for the right vocation, the right job, the right spouse, the right home—all in the hopes of finding meaning there.

Read Full Article
Humanum: Issues in Family, Culture & Science
Pontifical John Paul II Institute for Studies on Marriage and Family
620 Michigan Ave. N.E. (McGivney Hall)
Washington, DC 20064